Skip to main content
Category

Royal Society

Descartes and Vivisection

By Empiricism, Jesuit Theologians, Robert Boyle, Royal Society, Vesalius

Rene Descartes

Rene Descartes (1596-1650) opposed the traditional Scholastic philosophy of the universities, which at that time harboured an approach rooted in Aristotelianism as interpreted by the Christian Schoolmen. The Scholastics tended to identify their version of Aristotle with the Bible, maintaining that support for their exegesis could be found in Biblical text. Any refutation of Aristotle was thereby considered equivalent to blasphemy.
Descartes was born at La Haye, near Poitiers. His father was one of the French landed gentry, in a social situation where the clergy held prodigious political power alongside royalty. Descartes studied law at the University of Poitiers, gaining a degree. However, he did not pursue the career of a lawyer. After leaving military service, he lived a retiring existence in Holland, at places including Amsterdam and Leiden.
His major correspondent was Marin Mersenne (1588-1648), a theologian in contact with scientists and philosophers throughout Europe. Mersenne was a basic source of news for Descartes. The philosopher at first tended to take mathematics as the model for knowledge, an avenue demonstrated in his Rules for the Direction of the Mind. However, his basic field of endeavour is sometimes described in terms of natural philosophy, a subject contrasting with theology. Descartes developed a version of cosmology, employing a mechanistic physics.
In 1637, he published in French three scientific essays on optics, geometry, and meteorology. He was bypassing scholastic Latin. He did the same with his Discourse on Method, in which he elevated the “light of reason,” credited with the ability to distinguish between truth and falsity. That Discourse also emphasised a major difference between animals and humans; the distinction has since become a major source of disagreement. Descartes assumed an absence of mind in animals, comparing them to clock mechanisms.
In 1641, he published in Latin his Meditations on the First Philosophy. This became his most famous work. That book aroused objections from leading scholars and theologians. The author was basically in friction with Scholastic philosophy. His opponents included Calvinists. He was also in conflict with the trend of scepticism represented by Montaigne.
In 1644 appeared his Latin work Principia Philosophiae (Principles of Philosophy). This restates his version of metaphysics and also mechanistic physics. Descartes was in conflict with the Jesuit theologians or Late Scholastics, for example, Francisco Suarez. He was effectively pitched against Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas. In 1648, the curators of Leiden University confirmed their decision that only Aristotelian philosophy could be taught in their precincts. Professors in that establishment were forbidden to mention the name of Descartes.
The commentator has to be fair to the subject while observing his defects. Descartes was a mechanist who believed that he had evolved a perfect rationalism. This can be strongly queried, especially in view of the crude empiricism that emerges in the record of his activities. 
He even arranged [in 1646] for the slaughter of a pregnant cow so that he could examine the foetus at an early stage of its development. (Clarke 2006:332) 
Such actions were part of his insensitive approach to the issue of animal consciousness, encapsulated to some extent by his notorious theme that “animals are machines.” Descartes has been described as a pioneer of vivisection; he was by no means the only one. 
In 1646, an English royalist, namely William Cavendish (Duke of Newcastle), sent a letter to Descartes about the apparent ability of animals to think. The recipient made what appears to have been a reluctant concession. However, this occurred during his final years; the concession did not alter his basic standpoint. “This seems to me a very strong argument to prove that the reason animals do not speak is that they have no thought” (Clarke 2006:336). The reply of Descartes also included the reflection:
Though the animals do not perform any action which shows that they think, still, since the organs  of their body are not very different from ours, it may be conjectured that there is attached to those [animal] organs some thoughts such as we experience in ourselves, but of a very much less perfect kind. (Kenny translation, 1970)
The earlier letter of Descartes to Plempius, in February 1638, affords proof that he practised vivisection (Cottingham 1991:79-85). Descartes here described his vivisection of a living rabbit. Descartes also “wrote in correspondence that the mechanical understanding of animals absolved people of any guilt for killing and eating animals” (Animal Consciousness). His category of belief was very convenient for vivisectionists. The followers of Descartes, meaning Cartesians, are now criticised as the brutal precursors of widespread laboratory practice, which continues to masquerade as a perfect empirical science confounding the subject of animal ethics
Jesuits at this period may also have practised vivisection; certain references have been debated. A systematic approach to the theories of Descartes, on the part of his posthumous followers, led to the explicit support of vivisection. A case in point being Nicolas Malebranche (1638-1715), an influential neo-Cartesian mechanist who argued, on religious grounds, that animals lacked a soul and were incapable of pain or suffering, therefore being beyond any moral consideration. Some commentators express uncertainty as to whether Descartes himself believed this (Boden 2006:72). The fact is that Descartes performed animal experiments, to an unknown extent, and clearly believed that reference to vivisection was legitimate. 
Descartes ascribed sentience to animals. However, in contrast to Aristotelians, he explained sentience in mechanistic terms, eschewing concepts of a “sensitive” soul (Boden 2006:72). In his Discourse on Method (1637), Descartes stated that the divine gift of the soul distinguished humans from animals. Scientists found, in his writings, a reason to discount the behavioural response of animals to vivisection (Monamy 2009:10-11). 
A generally received idea is that Descartes followed no tradition, being committed to accept only what he learned firsthand. He was actually following the tradition of Vesalius in relation to dissection. The successors of Vesalius at Padua University had engaged in vivisection; the Fabrica of Vesalius has been shown to include this favoured practice. Descartes was also in support of conventional Christian doctrines about salvation of the soul, in which animals were not celebrated. His mechanist version of the universe was later proved erroneous. His physics transpired to be inadequate. A major anatomical theory of Descartes came under criticism: 

Descartes tried to explain most of our mental life in terms of processes involving the pineal gland, but the details remained unclear, even in his own eyes. (Stanford Encyclopedia

In 1629 he relocated to Amsterdam, then a new centre of anatomy, a fashionable Renaissance subject which he embraced. Descartes lived for a period in the Kalverstraat quarter, inhabited by butchers. He regularly visited the butcher stalls. While reading the works of Vesalius, he would purchase animal carcases, carrying these back to his flat for dissection. In a letter of 1639, after moving to other places, Descartes told Mersenne that he had spent much time in dissection for eleven years (Sawday 1995:147ff; McCance 2013:48-9). Such activities are questionable in the pursuit of a viable philosophy, despite the associations of a scientific revolution. Descartes was basically an empiricist, gaining disproportionate fame as a deductivist. The combination of tendencies proved a source of confusion. 
In 1632, Descartes wrote to Mersenne: “I am now dissecting the heads of various animals, so that I can explain what imagination, memory, etc. consist in” (Gaukroger 2000). His bland assumption, in respect of explanation, may be regarded as imaginative rather than anything more comprehensive. 
Descartes was preoccupied with both human and animal corpses, accomplishing “many post-mortem dissections.” He frequently visited abattoirs and the gallows (criminals were dissected after hanging). Not knowing where to stop, he followed the example of William Harvey (1578-1657) in vivisecting a few animals: fishes, eels, and a hare (Boden 2006:61). He describes the vivisection of a dog in his Description of the Human Body and of All Its Functions. Descartes does not there say that he performed the operation. However, some commentators have very feasibly construed that he did. Arguing against Harvey, the empiricist Descartes  affirms: “If you slice off the pointed end of the heart in a live dog, and insert a finger into one of the cavities…” (Cottingham 1985:317). The passage can easily offend dog lovers.
“There is no point in denying that Descartes’ vivisection and ill-treatment of animals is disgraceful” (Grayling 2006:159). The issue does not stop there. 
According to Richard Dawkins, Descartes “stood in a long tradition of vivisectionists including Galen and Vesalius, and he was followed by William Harvey and many others” (On Vivisection). His inspirer Vesalius was enthusiastic about the dissection of human corpses and animal vivisection. Vesalius (1514-64) authored the influential De humani corporis fabrica (1543). The word vivisection was not invented until 1702. The earlier word dissection can be equivocal in context.
Certain classical reports are alarming. The ancient Greek practitioners Herophilus and Erasistratus dissected (or vivisected) living human beings at Ptolemaic Alexandria. The sources are Aulus Cornelius Celsus (d.c. 50 AC) and Tertullian. The medic Herophilus (circa 320-260 BC) reputedly dissected at least 600 live prisoners, an operation endorsed by a monarch. The details have been disputed. In some directions, deniers of the sources are considered apologists for classicism. In his De Medicina, the Roman scholar Celsus affirms that Herophilus and his assistant “laid open living criminals” (Staden 1989:52). Herophilus influenced the “Empiricist” school of medicine, as distinguished from the “Rationalist” school of Hippocrates (ibid:50). Animal vivisection was a prevalent practice by the time of Galen (second century AC). 
As a philosopher, Descartes surely ought to have been more resistant to fashionable cruelty of the leisured class of scientists active in his own time. His inclination to the contrary places him in the same category as reprehensible events of the 1660s, when thirty vivisections were conducted in the presence of assembled members of the Royal Society in London. 
A well known early report of brutal Cartesian vivisectionists at the Port Royal School, in Paris, has aroused differences of interpretation. One commentary says the report “may not be trustworthy.” That account was written years after the events described. However, there are other reports of animal experiments in the late seventeenth century, along with implications that Cartesian mechanists made no attempt to minimise animal suffering, believing that this was an illusion (Boden 2006:72-3). 
The Port Royal report describes dogs being nailed alive to boards for dissection. This was during the 1650s. The callous behaviour is very easy to credit, as the Jansenist milieu under discussion is known to have been influenced by Cartesian attitudes, via leading figures at the Port Royal School and related Abbey. Someone had taught the pupils a Cartesian approach to supposed automata. The report was included in the Memoires of Nicolas Fontaine (1625-1709), a contribution which is very difficult to ignore (on the Port Royal School, see Delforges 1985).
Vivisection increased substantially as a consequence of Cartesian doctrine, being avidly practised by the Royal Society. This organisation was founded by a group of scientists including Robert Boyle (1627-91) and Robert Hooke (1635-1703). Their crimes are on record, including the injection of poisons, ever since a favoured device of  laboratory personnel. Dogs, sheep, and other animals were the victims. Hooke is known to have vivisected a dog in 1667, and in this respect was a virtual blood brother of Descartes.
Hooke’s prestigious colleague Robert Boyle was an ardent defender of vivisection, viewing critics as sentimentalists. How tough and supremely insensitive the empiricists were. The objectors were here viewed as “a discouraging impediment to the empire of man over the inferior creatures of God” (Boden 2006:73). 
The empire of man, considered so desirable by Boyle, was strongly convergent with developing inclinations for a colonial British Empire. The successors of the Romans (and the abominations of Galen) were eager to assert their scientific superiority over the supposed barbarians in the East (plus Africa and the Americas). The superiority and invasions can be strongly questioned. The mechanist use of brute force is no proof of cultural perfection. 
Boyle was a hero of the empiricist philosopher John Locke (1632-1704). The vivisectionist outlook evidently did influence Locke to some extent. An episode is reported, dating to the 1650s, of how he skinned a frog to prove circulation of blood. Though a mere scratch compared to agonies devised by the Royal Society, this detail is not attractive. Subsequently however, Locke recognised that animals could feel, moreover, that cruelty toward them is morally wrong. In Some Thoughts Concerning Education (1693), he advised that children should be reared to detest the mistreatment of animals, as a means to prevent cruelty against humans.
In this respect, Locke surpassed Spinoza, who recognised that animals feel, while remarking in Ethics that animals could be used as humans pleased. Locke can be compared to Aquinas, who much earlier concluded that cruelty to animals was evil, potentially leading to human victims. In the early years of Locke, the Puritans frowned upon blood sports in England, a mercy ending when Charles II re-established monarchical power.
A century after Boyle, the essayist Samuel Johnson (d.1784) complained about the “arts of torture” practised by some medical men, whose favoured pastime was “to nail dogs to tables and open them alive” (Boden 2006:73). Johnson was an opponent of slavery and a lover of cats. Elite members of the Royal Society continued experiments on live frogs, dogs, and horses. In more humane channels, the English gained a contradictory reputation as horse lovers. The clergyman Stephen Hales (1677-1761) was a partisan of Newtonian science at Cambridge. In 1714 he conducted dubious experiments on horses and dogs. Hales was elected a Fellow of the approving Royal Society in 1718. He afterwards turned his attention to plants and philanthropy. However, he continued to be praised for bleeding a sheep to death while measuring heartbeat. 

Not until the 1870s was official action taken to limit disturbing laboratory practices. The substantial continuation was not considered satisfactory by the National Anti-Vivisection Society, founded in that same decade. 
Bibliography:
Boden, Margaret A., Mind as Machine: A History of Cognitive Science Vol. 1 (Oxford University Press, 2006).
Clarke, Desmond M., Descartes: A Biography (Cambridge University Press, 2006).
Cottingham, John, et al, trans., The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (3 vols, Cambridge University Press, 1985-91).
Delforges, Frederic, Les Petites Ecoles de Port-Royal, 1637-1660 (Paris: Cerf, 1985).
Gaukroger, Stephen, et al, eds., Descartes’ Natural Philosophy (Abingdon: Routledge, 2000)
Grayling, A. C., Descartes (2005; London: Simon and Schuster, 2006).
Kenny, Anthony, trans., Descartes: Philosophical Letters (Oxford University Press, 1970).
McCance, Dawn, Critical Animal Studies: An Introduction (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2013).
Monamy, Vaughan, Experimentation: A Guide to the Issues (2000; second edn, Cambridge University Press, 2009).
Sawday, Jonathan, The Body Emblazoned: Dissection and the Human Body in Renaissance Culture (Abingdon: Routledge, 1995).
Shepherd, Kevin R. D., web article Rene Descartes Philosopher and Scientist (bibliography). 
Staden, Heinrich von, Herophilus: The Art of Medicine in Early Alexandria – Edition, translation, and essays (Cambridge University Press, 1989).
Kevin R. D. Shepherd 
February 2015, modified 2021

ENTRY no. 63 

Copyright © 2021 Kevin R. D. Shepherd. All Rights Reserved.